QUANTUM MECHANICS : THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS
(Part2)
Quantum
Agents
This problem of the indeterminateness of the conscious choices is
resolved in orthodox Copenhagen
quantum mechanics by adopting a pragmatic stance. The theory is considered to
be a set of rules useful to a community of communicating, conscious, observing
agents imbedded in a physical universe. These agents make conscious decisions
about how to probe that universe, in order to observe responses that will augment
their knowledge. The difficulty mentioned above, which is that the known laws
do not determine which of the possible probing questions will be physically
posed, is neatly resolved by saying that this very openness allows the conscious agents to freely choose
which probing questions they will physically pose. Thus the causal gap in the
mathematically described structure is filled by the free choices made by conscious
agents.
Bohr often emphasized the freedom of these agents to make these
choices:
The freedom of experimentation, presupposed in classical physics, is of course retained and corresponds to the free choice of experimental arrangement for which the mathematical structure of the quantum mechanical formalism offers the appropriate latitude. (Bohr, 1958, p.73).
To my mind there is no other alternative than to admit in this field of experience, we are dealing with individual phenomena and that our possibilities of handling the measuring instruments allow us to make a choice between the different complementary types of phenomena that we want to study. (Bohr, 1958, p. 51).
These quotes highlight the key fact
that selection of the Process 1 probing events is determined, within the framework
of contemporary physics, not by known mathematical or physical laws but rather
by free choices made by conscious agents.
Von Neumann’s Move
John von Neumann formulated Copenhagen quantum
mechanics in a mathematically rigorous form, and then, in order to remove
ambiguities associated with the placement of the Heisenberg cut, showed that
this cut could be pushed all the way up, so that the entire physically
describable universe, including the bodies and brains of the agents, are
described quantum mechanically. This placement of the cut does not eliminate
the need for Process 1. It merely places the physical aspect of the Process 1
psychophysical event in the brain of the conscious agent, while placing the
conscious choice of which probing question to pose in his stream of
consciousness. That is, the conscious act of choosing
the probing question is represented as a psychologically described event in the
agent’s mind, which is called by von Neumann (1955, p. 421) the “abstract ego”. This choice is physically and functionally implemented by a Process 1 action in his
brain. The psychologically described and physically described actions are the
two aspects of a single psychophysical event, whose physically described aspect
intervenes in the orderly Process 2 evolution in a mathematically well defined
way.
Bohr emphasized that the laws of
quantum theory should continue to be valid in biological systems, but that the
latitude introduced by the severe constraints upon observation imposed by the
demands of sustaining life could permit such concepts such as “teleology” and
“volition” to come consistently into
play. (Bohr, 1958, p.10, p.22)
Interactive dualism
Orthodox quantum theory is a
theory of a type called interactive dualism, which goes back in modern philosophy
to Descartes, and before that to the ancient Greeks. An interactive dualism
postulates the existence of two entirely different kinds of realities, mental
and physical, that interact. Mental realities have the character of feelings, broadly construed to include
thoughts, ideas, perceptions, pains, joys, sorrows and all things that enter
directly into our streams of conscious experiences, and are described basically
in psychological language. Physical realities are elements that are described
in our theories of nature in terms of mathematical qualities assigned to
space-time points.
Interactive dualism combined with the precepts
of classical physics gives classical
interactive dualism. This has been attacked ferociously by philosophers for
over three hundred years, with an intensity that has been increasing over the
past half century. Quantum interactive dualism is based, instead, on orthodox (von
Neumann) quantum theory.
The first main objection to
classical interactive dualism is that it postulates the existence of two
entirely different kinds of things, but provides no understanding of how they
interact, or even can interact. The second main objection is that the physical
description is, by itself, already causally complete, giving a completely
deterministic account of the evolution in time of every physically described
entity, which means that the mental realities have nothing to do, and no possibility
of influencing anything physical. The mental side is a “ghost in the machine”
that is imagined to be pulling the levers in order to ‘work its will’ in the
physical world, but cannot really be doing so because the behavior of the
physically described universe is completely determined independently of the
ghostly machinations.
Quantum interactive dualism neatly
evades both objections. The answer to the first is that the form of the interaction
between the mentally and physically described aspects of nature is specified in von Neumann’s account of
the measurement process. This account is part of a careful mathematical
description of the fundamental principles of quantum theory, and of how they
are to be employed in practice. The specification of the form of the
interaction between the two differently described aspects is an essential part
of von Neumann’s formulation of quantum theory. It is essential because quantum
theory is specifically designed to be a tool that allows physicists to make
computations that connect their experiences about setting up probing experiments
to their expectations about the observable responses to these probing actions. Such
a theory requires an adequate theory of measurement and observation, which von
Neumann provides.
As regards the second objection,
a huge essential difference between the classical and quantum dualities is that
in the quantum case the physically described part is not causally complete.
Something else is needed to complete the dynamics. Mental realities function both
to complete the causal structure and also to undergird what the theory is
basically about, namely the structural relationships between the elements in
our streams of conscious experiences.
In my characterization of
interactive dualism I spoke of two kinds of realities,
physical and mental. Mental realities are certainly real: a presently felt pain
really does exist. The experiencings of theoretical ideas in the streams of
consciousness of physicists are also real happenings. But the existence in nature of real entities
that have all the properties ascribed by the precepts of classical physics to,
say, “electrons” would be surely denied by most quantum physicists. Quantum
philosophy recommends avoiding commitment to the idea that there are realities
in nature that accurately conform to our theoretical ideas about the physical
universe. In regard to the physical it is only the descriptions themselves, and the way that they are used, that are ascribed
significance in orthodox quantum philosophy. Ontological commitments pertaining
to the physical are not part of science. In general, the practical meanings of
descriptions are defined in the end by how the descriptions are used in
practice.
The fact that the form of the
interaction between the psychologically and physically described aspects of
quantum theory is specified is important: it severely constrains the theory. Arbitrary
ad hoc proposals cannot be postulated willy nilly. For example, many proposals
are ruled out by the fact the living brain is large, warm, and wet, and
interacts strongly with its environment. The first, and very stringent, demand
on any serious proposal is that it work in this hostile-to-quantum-effects
setting.
The only pertinent quantum effect known to me that survives robustly under
these hostile settings is the quantum Zeno effect, so-named because of its
rough similarity to the paradox that claims that the hare can never catch the
turtle because, by the time the hare reaches where the turtle was, the turtle
will have moved on. That claim is obviously false. But there is a vaguely
similar claim about quantum mechanics that is unquestionably true (Misra,
1977). If, under appropriate conditions, one repeatedly poses the same probing
question at a sufficiently rapid rate, then the sequence of responses will tend
to get stuck in place. In the limit of arbitrarily rapid re-posings, the
response will become frozen: all the responses will come out to be the same,
even though very strong physical forces may be working to make them change.
Thus a manipulation of the timings of
the probing actions, which are under the control of the consciousness of agent,
can have, even in a warm, wet brain,
a very special kind of physical effect. If, by mental effort, an agent can
cause a sufficient increase in probing
rate, then that agent can cause a state of intention and attention to be
held in place much longer than would be the case if no such effort were being made.
The crucial point, here, is that
the physically-described laws of quantum mechanics do not fix the times at which the physical Process 1
probing actions occur, or what these
physical probing actions will be. This lacuna is the essential reason why the
conscious “free choices” on the part of human agents were brought into quantum
mechanics by its founders, and were retained by John von Neumann! These conscious choices control the timings of
the physical Process 1 events studied by Misra and Sudarshan, and this connection
entails, in principle, the capacity of these psychologically described aspects of
the streams of consciousness of agents to control, via quantum Zeno holding
actions, certain physically described features of the world.
Huge survival benefits could
accrue to agents that can exploit this feature of the quantum mechanics,
because this intentional stabilizing of attention would hold in place also the
corresponding pattern of functional brain activity.
Such a holding effect could, of
course, be postulated, ad hoc, to occur in a classical-physics-based
model. But in that case the holding effect would not be a direct consequence of
the same basic psychophysical laws that are used by physicists to explain
atomic phenomena. In the quantum case the holding effect is probably the only robust
kind of effect of mind on brain that the theory predicts, whereas any desired
regularity could postulated in a theory that simply adds mind ad hoc. As
regards classical-physics-based theories, the view of physicists is that
classical physics is an approximation
to quantum physics. All effects of conscious thought upon brain activity that follow from quantum theory, such as the
quantum Zeno holding effect, are eliminated in the classical physics
approximation, because in that approximation the uncertainty-principle-based latitude
within which the causal effects of mind upon the physically described aspects
of nature operate shrinks to zero.
Comparison to psychological findings
The dynamical effect described
above of a volition-induced high rapidity of the Process 1 probing actions is exactly
in line with the description of the effects of volition described by William
James (1892). In the section entitled Volitional
effort is effort of attention he writes:
Thus we find that we reach the heart of our inquiry into volition
when we ask by what process is it that the thought of any
given action comes to prevail stably in the mind. (p. 417)
The essential achievement of will, in short, when it is most
‘voluntary,’ is to attend to a difficult object and hold it fast
before the mind. (p.417). Everywhere, then, the function of effort is the same: to keep
affirming and adopting the thought which, if left to itself, would slip away.(p.421)
James may have foreseen, on the
basis of his efforts to understand the mind-brain connection, the eventual downfall
of classical mechanics. He closed his book
with the prophetic words
…and never forget that the natural-science assumptions with which we started are provisional and revisable things. (p.433)
A lot has happened in psychology
since the time of William James, but these newer developments support James’s
idea of the holding-attention-in-place action of volition. Much of the recent empirical
and theoretical work pertaining to attention is summarized in Harold Pashler’s
book The Psychology of Attention
(Pashler, 1998). Pashler concluded that the evidence indicates the existence of
two distinct kinds of mental processes, one that appears not to involve
volition, and that allows several perceptual processes to proceed in parallel
without significant interference, and one that does involve volition and that
includes planning and memory storage. This latter process seems to involve a linear
queuing effect with limited total capacity.
These properties of volition-driven
processes appear to be explainable in
terms of the basic laws of orthodox quantum physics, which entail the existence
of Process 1 physical events whose timings are controlled by conscious choices,
and which can, in principle, by means of the quantum Zeno effect, tend to hold
in place a pattern of neural activity that will tend to bring into being an
intended effect. But this holding effect drops out in the classical-physics
approximation, in which all physically described properties become completely
determined by physically described properties alone, with consciousness a
causally inert, or causally superfluous, bystander. Correlations between physically and psychologically described properties
can be described within a classical physics based framework, but the
psychologically described aspects will remain essentially epiphenomenal
by-products of brain activity.
This evidence from psychology is
discussed in detail in Stapp (1999, 2001) and in Schwartz, Stapp, and
Beauregard (2003, 2005)
Application in Neuroscience
The most direct evidence
pertaining to the effects of conscious choices upon brain processes comes from
experiments in which identifiable consciously controllable cognitive processes seem to be controlling directly measured
physical processes in the brain. An example is the experiment of Ochsner et.al.
(2001). The subjects are trained how to cognitively re-evaluate emotional
scenes by consciously creating and holding in place an alternative fictional
story of what is really happening in connection with a scene they are viewing.
The trial began with
a 4 sec presentation of a negative or neutral photo, during which participants
were instructed simply to view the stimulus on the screen. This interval was
intended to provide time for participants to apprehend complex scenes and allow
an emotional response to be generated that participants would then be asked to
regulate. The word Attend (for negative or neutral photos) or Reappraise
(negative photos only) then appeared beneath the photo and the participants
followed this instruction for 4 sec …
To verify whether the
participants had, in fact, reappraised in this manner, during the post-scan
rating session participants were asked to indicate for each photo whether they
had reinterpreted the photo (as instructed) or had used some other type of
reappraisal strategy. Compliance was high: On less than 4% of trials with
highly negative photos did participants report using another type of strategy.
Reports such as these can be
taken as evidence that the streams of conscious of the participants do exist
and contain elements identifiable as efforts to reappraise.
Patterns of brain activity
accompanying reappraisal were assessed by using functional magnetic imaging
resonance (fMRI). The fMRI results were that reappraisal was positively
correlated with increased activity in the left lateral prefrontal cortex and the
dorsal medial prefrontal cortex (regions
thought to be connected to cognitive control) and decreased activity in the
(emotion-related) amygdala and medial orbito-frontal cortex.
How can we understand and explain
the psychophysical correlations exhibited in this experiment?
According to the quantum model,
the conscious feelings cause the
changes in brain activity to occur. This causation is in strict conformity to the
known laws of physics, as spelled out in von Neumann’s book Mathematical Foundations of Quantum
Mechanics.
This causal explanation, this
whole causal story, falls apart if one tries to explain this psychophysical correlation
within the framework of the classical approximation. That approximation
entirely eliminates the effects of our conscious choices and efforts upon the
physical world, including our brains. But what is the rational motivation for
insisting on using this approximation? The applicability of the classical
approximation to this phenomenon certainly does not follow from physics
considerations: calculations based on the known properties of nerve terminals indicate
that quantum theory must in principle be used. Nor does it follow from the fact
that classical physics works reasonable well in neuroanatomy or neurophysiology:
Quantum theory explains why the classical approximation works well in those domains.
Nor does it follow rationally from the massive analyses and conflicting arguments
put forth by philosophers of mind. In view of the turmoil that has engulfed
philosophy during the three centuries since Newton cut the bond between mind and matter, the
re-bonding achieved by physicists during the first half of the twentieth
century must be seen as an enormous development: a lifting of the veil. Ignoring
this huge and enormously pertinent development in basic science, and proclaiming
the validity of materialism on the basis of inapplicable-in-this-context
nineteenth century science is not a rational judgment.
Of course, one can simply abandon
the idea that ideas can actually cause
anything physical, and view the feeling of effort as not a cause, but rather an effect,
of a prefrontal excitation that causes the suppression of the limbic response,
and that is caused entirely by other purely physical activities.
Viewed from a sufficiently narrow
perspective that might seem to be a satisfactory conclusion, but it leads to
the old problem: why is consciousness present at all, and why does it feel so
causally efficacious, if it has no causal efficacy at all? Why this big hoax? Quantum theory answers:
There is no a hoax! It was only the premature acceptance a basically false physical
theory, fundamentally inapplicable to the brain, that ever made it seem so!
The only objections I know to applying the
basic principles of physics to brain dynamics are, first, the forcefully
expressed opinions of some non-physicists that the classical approximation provides
an entirely adequate foundation for understanding brain dynamics, in spite of the
quantum calculations that indicate the opposite; and, second, the opinions of
some physicists that the hugely successful orthodox quantum theory, which is
intrinsically dualistic, should, for philosophical reasons, be replaced by some
theory that re-converts human consciousness into a causally inert witness to the
mindless dance of atoms. Neither of
these opinions has any secure scientific basis.
There are several other quantum
theories of consciousness, but all of them are based on von Neumann’s work. The
physics considerations described above rest completely on that work. I shall describe
next some proposals that go far beyond von Neumann’s secure base, and introduce
some very controversial ideas.
Electron - energy and Information.
ReplyDelete===
There's a relationship between information and energy.
The amount of information is related to the amount of energy
needed to receive the message.
#
What is the essence of energy-information?
The essence of the energy-information is an electron.
Electron is the smallest bit of energy-information.
#
Information is transferred through EM waves.
There isn't EM wave without electron. (H. Lorentz)
#
''Information is the new atom or electron,
the fundamental building block of the universe . . .
We now see the world as entirely made of information:
it's bits all the way down.''
/ Bryan Appleyard /
#
''It is important to realize that in physics today,
we have no knowledge of what energy is.
We do not have a picture that energy comes
in little blobs of a definite amount. It is not that way.''
/ Richard Feynman about an electron /
===
Electron is a quantum of information.
Electron is a keeper of information.
Why?
An electron has six ( 6 ) formulas:
E=h*f and e^2=ah*c ,
+E=Mc^2 and -E=Mc^2 ,
E=-me^4/2h*^2= -13,6eV and E= ∞ . . . .
and obeys five (5) Laws :
a) The Law of conservation and transformation energy/ mass
b) The Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle / Law
c) The Pauli Exclusion Principle/ Law
d) Dirac - Fermi statistic
e) Maxwell / Lorentz EM law
It means in different actions electron must know six different formulas
and must observe five laws. To behave in such different
conditions a single electron itself must be a keeper of information.
#
Michael Brooks:
'‘ The laws of physics dictate that information, like energy,
cannot be destroyed, which means it must go somewhere.'’
/ Book ‘ The big questions’. Page 195-196. /
It means an electron (as a little blobs of a definite amount of energy)
even in different situations never loses its information.
#
- "Do Electrons Think?" (BBC 1949)
/ Erwin Schrödinger /
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=hCwR1ztUXtU
#
Erwin Schrödinger asked: - "Do Electrons Think?"
In my opinion, if an electron can keep
different information it means an electron has memory.
If an electron has memory then one single and free electron
has ability to use his memory for thinking.
(but scientists have ability to manipulate with electron's free will.)
==============